On Certain Clause Types [a 1984 working paper on ergativity]
University of Melbourne
Linguistics
Section
Faculty
of Arts
Working
Papers in Linguistics
No.
10, December 1984: 57-68
On
Certain Clause Types
Probal
Dasgupta
Deccan College, Pune 411006, India
1.
This is very much a working paper. I will assume some of the small clause
theory developed by Kayne, Stowell, Pesetsky and other GB syntacticians, and
make proposals about certain types of clause structure within a variant of the
GB framework. The point is to explore certain elaborations of GB in a way
which, I hope, will seem fruitful and therefore will provoke criticism and
correction. My proposals in their present form are almost certainly wrong, and
therefore I have compressed this presentation as much as possible, to avoid
taking up too much of your time.
2.
Schwartz (see the bibliography for all references) has claimed that there is a
significant difference between the ergative and accusative clause types: while
the latter may be VSO, SVO, or SOV, the former may only be VSO or SOV, never
SVO. (With apologies to Hixkaryana, I will stick to the major types and ignore
VOS, OVS, and OSV.) I am told by as eminent an ergativologist as Dixon that, indeed, there
are no well-known SVO languages with syntactic ergativity; let us assume that
there are none at all, and proceed. Since languages are not terribly rigid
about favouring this or that clause type, let us speak of clause types and not
of language types. Now, why is Schwartz’s generalization real? How do SVO order
and syntactic ergativity clash? I will offer what amounts to an answer to this
question.
[p
58:] 3. This answer makes no sense without a wider setting. What goes on in a
clause? Let us, to be concrete, propose an exact representation:
(1)
[S”NP-topic
[S’NP-focus [S’Comp [SNP-subject [PredPInfl
VP]]]]]
I
will assume, with Kayne and others, that PredP is Infl’ and that S is Infl”,
and that S’ is Comp’. I am adding the assumption that S” is Comp”. The
assumption that a focus is adjoined to S’ is made in Baltin’s thesis and
related work. By parity, we may propose that some languages are going to have a
focus adjoined to PredP which, being Infl’, is parallel to Comp’; this proposal
makes sense in the predominantly SOV languages of South
Asia, at least, but will not be pursued here. I am merely focusing
on the point that Infl and Comp seem to be deeply similar. If they are, the
Topic GF, [NP, S”], is on a par with the Subject GF, [NP, S]. I would like to
propose that these are not D-structure GFs. D-Structure is a pure
representation of Theta Roles. Notions like Topic and Focus involve Iota
States, where iota stands for the system of Introduction, introducing
New material in relation to Given material in a discourse, just as theta stands
for the THematic system. Assume that Subject, being structurally
parallel to Topic on our assumptions, also involves Iota States. If Move Alpha
in syntax maps theta representations onto mixed theta-iota representations, it
follows that all material in Subject, Focus or Topic positions at S-structure
must have come there by movement. Not only does this assimilate Move NP (to
Subject) and Move Wh (to Focus or Topic); this also says that ordinary subjects
of clauses, without raising or passive, become subjects by moving into
subject position. Subject-Infl agreement, Williams-coindexing between subject
and predicate, Nominative Case Assignment – all this must take place or be
checked at S-structure.
[p
59:]4. Where do subjects come from? What is their canonical D-structure
position? Initially, let us make the standard GB assumption that subjects,
unlike objects, are indirectly theta-marked and thus are outside the
‘real’ VP comprising the V and its complements. Suppose I postulate:
(2)
[PredPInfl [VPNP
VP]
Let
the NP in (2) be the D-structure subject. Given this configuration, we
may propose that, in a typical VSO language, V moves to Infl, accounting for
the surface facts, and that, in an SVO or SOV language, NP moves to what
(1) calls the subject position and antecedent-governs its trace, which is made
possible by the fact that the ‘broad VP’ (which contains NP and the
‘narrow VP’) is not a maximal projection.
5.
The broad VP of (2) is technically a small clause with NP as its
‘subject’ in the sense of the work of Stowell, Kayne, etc. I am not proposing a fresh modification of X’
theory.
6.
The narrow VP, under orders from its V, assigns the Agent theta role to its
sister NP, or tells this NP to be an expletive pro. The
relevant sense of Agent is problematic (in John understands the problem,
is John an Agent or an Experiencer?), but that is an unsolved problem of
long standing.
7.
So much for one clause type. (2) is the basic story for accusative clauses, and
for such variants as unaccusative clauses like The stick broke, in which
we need to say something about what theta role the V assigns to its deep object
and S-structure subject; I will take all that as done. Let us proceed to
syntactically ergative clauses, for which (2) fails. Let us try (3):
(3)
[VP[NP3NP1
NP2] V]
[p
60:] Assume that only VP can assign the Agent theta role. In (3), V can only
assign Theme, which it assigns to the small clause NP3 and thus to
its head NP2. If we take NP3 V to be an ‘unaccusative’
structure in that V assigns no Case to NP3, then NP3 must
move:
(4)
[SNP3
PredP]
The
Infl head of PredP will assign Absolutive to NP3 and thus to its
head NP2. This still leaves NP1 unroled and uncased. NP1
must therefore take care of itself. It must bear Ergative Case. We may say that
NP1 is really, throughout, a PP with a special kind of P, an
Ergative Case desinence, which expresses Agent theta role, and, like Locative
and other ‘concrete’ Case desinences (cf. the work of Kurylowicz on ‘concrete’
Cases, and the discussion of this work in my 1985 paper), is ‘self-appointed’.
Another option is to move NP1 and form (5),
(5)
[SNP1
S]
and
then to let NP1 in this new position receive Ergative Case, either
by invoking a rule like the Genitive Rule or by letting the S sister of the NP1
position in (5) assign this Case. If Ergative Case always has an Agent reading,
the Logical Form will then come out right.
8.
How do we get the Ergative phrase to receive Agent theta role? Surely we don’t
want to stipulate that Ergative Case expresses this role. Since agentive verbs
like hit and read in general are indirect assigners of the Agent
theta role, we expect this lexical property to play a role in ergative clauses
too. In an accusative clause with an agentive V, the VP projected by this V
theta-marks its NP sister in the broad VP shown in (2). But, in an
ergative clause, VP has no NP sister. Recall that NP3 moves to the
position shown in (4), where PredP contains only Infl and [p 61] the VP (3).
Thus the usual mechanism of indirect theta-marking through V is rendered
inoperative. Assume that in such a case VP passes on its indirect theta-marking
ability to the next maximal projection, S. Thus, S, on V’s behalf, theta-marks
its sister NP1 in (5). It was suggested in paragraph 7 (as a second
possibility) that S also Case-marks NP1; perhaps, specifically, an S
can Case-mark such an NP sister if it theta-marks this NP. Hence the
association of Agent theta role and Ergative Case. No stipulation is needed.
9.
The proposal of paragraph 7 says that NP1 receives no theta role in
its D-structure position in (3), but is theta-marked only in its S-structure
position shown in (5). If this is rejected as conceptually unsound, we may
propose instead that in (3) the NP2 head of NP3 and the V
compositionally theta-mark NP1; cf. the standard account of joint
theta-marking by V and P in [V [P NP]]. Then NP1 in (5) receives
Ergative Case by other means, e.g. structural Case assignment, the first
possibility suggested in paragraph 7. This solution would be more in keeping
with the GB style than that of paragraph 8. While I will stick to paragraph 8
here, the question remains open.
10.
In syntactically ergative clauses, NP2 has some subject properties,
e.g. the ability to control the PRO subject of an adverbial clause. How does
this come about? Consider (4). NP2 heads NP3, which, as
the daughter of S in (4), is supposed to have some subject properties.
11.
R. Kayne has pointed out that my account needs to be supplemented by an answer
to the following question: How is it that no ergative language has S-structures
such as (6)? If I cannot answer this question, I have, in effect, said nothing
about Schwartz’s generalization.
(6)
[NP1
Infl [VPV [NP3 t1 NP2]]]
[p
62:] Try some elaborations of (6). It is clear that (7) is out:
(7)
[SNP1
[PredP Infl [VPV [NP3 t1 NP2]]]
We
want NP1 and NP2 to be Ergative and Absolutive,
respectively, and in (7) Infl doesn’t govern NP2 and does govern NP1.
Thus (7) is not a possible ‘SVO clause’ representation. Try (8) now:
(8)
[SNP1
[S[PredPInfl [VPV t3]][NP3
t1 NP2]]]
One
should be able to make this work; NP2 agrees with, and is assigned
Absolutive Case by, Infl; NP1 is the Ergative phrase; theta-marking
is as in my account of (3)-(5). Why is there, apparently, no ergative language
like this?
12.
In English, where a lexical (or non-lexical) head precedes its complements,
forming H’, the specifier, if any, precedes H’, forming H”, as noted in Remarks
on nominalization. If PredP is Infl’ and S is Infl”, the subject is the
specifier of Infl’ and should precede Infl’. This canon is violated by (8),
where the specifier NP3 follows the Infl’ (the PredP). This is not a
theoretical answer, of course, but it is a starting point. There are several
moves one can imagine making. One would be to say: English is a head-first
language; Kayne and others have taken part in a process of turning specifier
positions into head positions (e.g. Infl and Comp used to be regarded as
specifiers), helping to reduce ‘Specifier precedes Head-bar’ to a case of ‘Head
precedes Complement’; to take the process further, some people have proposed
that the Topic position heads S”; going back to (1), since Subject parallels
Topic, perhaps the Subject position heads S, to extend the innovative idea of a
position type (rather than a category) heading a projection (the idea
that Topic is the head of S” is due, I seem to recall, to Guéron and May), not
an implausible idea, for the notion of Infl and Comp heads already extends head
theory to permit a function to head a [p 63:] projection (notice that
Infl and Comp, as functors, are not ‘categories’ like NP as distinct from
functions like ‘Subject’ in the sense of the classic discussion of this matter
in Aspects), and the idea of Topic heading S” or Subject heading S only
makes fuller use of this already proposed innovation. This move, or series of
moves, entails the interesting consequence that (8) violates the Empty Category
Principle. Consider NP3 and its trace t3. The lexical
head V, which governs t3, starts a g-projection set, in the sense of
Kayne’s recent (and still current) work on connectedness. Infl canonically
governs VP in this head-first language, permitting the g-projection set to
proceed to PredP, the maximal projection of Infl on the new assumption that S
is a projection of subject and not of Infl. Now, NP3 is on the
incorrect branch: it fails to canonically govern PredP; thus, the g-projection
set initiated by the lexical governor of t3 does not contain the
antecedent of t3; the ECP is violated. In contrast, take (9), the
result of packing (3) and Infl into (4) and (4) into (5):
(9)[SNP1
[S[NP3 t1 NP2][PredP[VP
t3 V] Infl]]]
This
respects the Kayne version of the ECP, as the reader can verify, as far as t3
is concerned. There is a problem with t1, for NP2 is not
a lexical head and Infl on my assumptions cannot govern NP3 and thus
cannot govern into it; but my hunch is that the ‘theta route’ from V to the
narrow S (which, on V’s behalf, theta-marks its sister NP1) saves t1.
Assume that V hands the theta job over to VP, which passes it on to PredP,
which passes it on to the narrow S; this gives Infl, or even V, an access to
(and into) NP3 which it otherwise would not have. Alternatively, NP1
in its new position antecedent-governs and thus sanctions t1 by
governing across the NP3 boundary and ignoring the S boundary if we
may assume that the narrow S and the broad S are ‘the same projection’ and that
therefore NP1 (a) heads it and (b) does not see the narrow S as a [p
64:] boundary; if this is licit, we don’t need g-projections for t1.
13.
One may ask a very different question. Why not assume that (7) is the
representation of English John loves Mary? Why start with (2) and not
(10) as the D-structure level in English?
(10)
[PredPInfl [VPV [NP3 NP1 NP2]]]
Once
we are willing, on the basis of the considerations outlined above, to accept
(9) as an ergative S-structure, we may consider giving up our initial
assumption that accusative clauses have the quite different D-structure (2).
Perhaps all D-structures have a VP consisting of V and, if there are two
arguments, a small clause comprising these arguments. An S-structure like (7)
will ensue. Let us work this out.
14.
The issues are slightly sharper in a language like Hindi, with SOV order and
split morphological ergativity: the Theme has no syntactic subject properties
(does not control into adverbial clauses, bind reflexives, etc.) but controls
Infl agreement when the V is a past participle, forcing the Agent into the
‘morphologically ergative’ or Agentive Case (marked by the Postposition ne);
when the V is in some other form, we have a straightforward accusative clause.
Let us, then, explore the idea that (11) is the D-structure and (12) the
S-structure for Hindi ra:m ciTThi: likhega: “Ram letter will.write” ‘Ram
will write a letter’.
(11)
[PredP[VP[NP3 [NP1 ra:m][NP2
ciTThi:]][Vlikhe]]ga:]]
(12)
[S[NP1 ra:m][PredP [NP3 t1[NP2 ciTThi:]][Vlikhe]][ga:]]]
15.
While retaining the GB idea of Infl and VP as a leading idea, I have
implemented it somewhat unusually: in [p 65:] (11) and (12) I show the V node
as dominating the verb stem likh and the mood marker e, leaving
the unlabelled node after it (you may call it Infl, but only if you remember
that I am cutting the pie differently) dominating only the tense-agreement
marker ga:. As Infl heads PredP, it can, being partly nominal, impose
Agr on its complement VP, explaining the occurrence of Agr features on V; this
is analogous, on my assumptions, to the way the Subject, head of S, imposes its
Agr features on PredP in general and on PredP’s head Infl in particular. In my
view, different ‘moods of V’ (subjunctive dekhe, imperfect dekhta:,
perfect dekha:) are slightly different categories within the broad
archicategory ‘V’. This will have to be left for proper treatment elsewhere.
16.
Assuming, then, that ga: is Infl in (11)-(12), let us note that V
assigns Objective Case and Theme theta role to NP3 (and its head NP2)
but lends its agentivity to the VP, which, having no sister, lends to the PredP
this job of assigning Agent theta role to an Agent NP. This is how ra:m
gets its theta role. Assume than an element E can theta-mark (on its own or on
some other element’s behalf) a constituent C iff E Case-marks C. Assume that
‘lending’ the ability to assign a particular theta role is a real phenomenon,
and that an element E will assign Case in accordance with its own nature (PredP
assigns Nominative/ Absolutive; S assigns Agentive/ Ergative; V assigns
Objective). Assume that, in a syntactically ergative language, V does not
assign Case (and therefore must lend its theta roles), and that, if a V lends
two theta-marking abilities to VP, i.e. Theme and Agent, then the usual
inner-outer distribution with Theme inside and Agent outside will be respected
(for reasons not yet understood), i.e. in an ergative clause the PredP will end
up assigning the Theme theta role and the S, the Agent theta role. On these
assumptions, many problems dissolve, and we can even derive as a theorem a
version of Burzio’s generalization (cf. Chomsky 1981) that a V which does not
[p 66:] Case-mark its object cannot indirectly theta-mark its subject position:
the point, recast in this framework, is that an ‘unaccusative’ V, which takes
an NP but does not Case-mark (and therefore does not theta-mark) this NP, will
either take an NP3, a small clause, or just an NP2, a
bare theme. In the former case, the V will, in our terms, lend its Theme and Agent
theta-marking abilities upwards, with the consequences we have seen. In the
latter case, which Burzio was concerned with, the V’s theta grid has just a
Theme, no Agent.
17.
Returning to (12), we see, then, that ra:m gets Nominative Case and
Agent theta role from PredP, while ciTThi: is Case-marked and
theta-marked by V. Consider now a morphologically ergative structure:
(13)
[S[NP1 ra:m ne][S[NP3 t1
[NP2 ciTThi:]][PredP[VP t3 [Vlikhi:]][Infl
hai]]]]
Ram AGENTIVE letter.Fem written.Fem
is
‘Ram
has written a letter’
The
perfect mood of the V, as mentioned in paragraph 15, is a specific
category (although called ‘V’), like the subjunctive dekhe of (12), with
a categorial feature bundle of its own (for some proposals about an adequate
theory of categorial features, see my forthcoming Deccan College Bulletin
paper); a perfect mood V, unlike a subjunctive mood V, cannot assign Case. Therefore,
on our assumptions, it cannot do its own theta-marking either, but must lend
both the Theme and the Agent of its theta grid to VP, which lends them to
PredP, which takes the lower member of the hierarchy (the Theme), ciTThi:,
assigns Theme theta role and Nominative Case, and lends the Agent-marking job
to S, which theta-marks and Case-marks its NP1 sister; hence the
Agent theta role and Agentive Case of ra:m ne.
[p
67:] 18. On this account, morphological ergativity involves a particular ‘form
of a V’ (a particular category in the V family) being unable to assign Case,
and syntactic ergativity, we may assume, involves an inability on the part of V
in general, as an archicategory, to assign Case. This is the parameter. If V in
an ergative system never assigns Case, canonical alignments change, so that
PredP canonically assigns Absolutive Case and Theme theta role, making it a
regular pattern for S to assign Ergative Case and Agent theta role. Arguably,
the canonical position of NP sister of PredP is locus of classical ‘subject
properties’; hence the facts of Dyirbal or Central Arctic Eskimo. As a matter
of fact, ergativologists say that all ergative languages have accusative
enclaves. Perhaps these are like Hindi’s ergative enclave. Just as some moods
in the Hindi V ‘switch Case off’, perhaps some regions in the V system of a
syntactically ergative language ‘switch Case on’, producing a superficial
deviance from the patterns that are canonical in the language.
19.
All this will have to pass the test of the passive and anti-passive patterns
carefully studied by relational grammarians. I don’t yet have enough to say
about these constructions. As is indicated by my calling hai ‘is’ in
(13) an Infl, I assume that auxiliary elements start out in Infl; perhaps a
passive PredP is of the form [PredPPredP Infl] in Hindi and
correspondingly [PredPInfl PredP] in English; perhaps John is
good has a D-structure like [PredP[Inflis][John
good]], where [John good] is a small clause. More work is obviously needed so
that this model can be fleshed out and criticized seriously. Meanwhile, it is
surely a straightforward task to work out the consequences of my assumptions
for the analysis of well-studied languages like English and French, which are
not all that different from Hindi. And surely linguists who are familiar with
ergative languages can tell, as grammarians, whether what I am saying ‘sounds
right’.
[p
68:]Bibliography
Baltin,
Mark R. 1978. Towards a theory of movement rules. MIT Ph.D. dissertation.
Chomsky,
Noam. 1981. Lectures on government and binding. Dordrecht: Foris.
Dasgupta,
Probal. In press (1985). On Bangla nouns. Indian Linguistics 46:1-2.
Dasgupta,
Probal. Forthcoming (1986). Gerunds, participles and the theory of categories.
Bulletin of Deccan College Research Institute.
Kayne,
Richard S. 1984. Connectedness and binary branching. Dordrecht: Foris.
Kuryłowicz,
Jerzy. 1960. Esquisses linguistiques. Wroclaw and Krakow: Wydawnictwo Polskiej
Akademii Nauki. Especially pp 131-50, Le problème du classement des cas.
Pesetsky,
David. 1982. Paths and categories. MIT Ph.D. dissertation.
Schwartz,
Arthur. 1972. The VP constituent of SVO languages. In John P. Kimball, ed.,
Syntax and Semantics Vol. 1. New York: Seminar Press.
Stowell,
Tim. 1983. Subjects across categories. The Linguistic Review 2.285-312.
Colophon
Some
stimulating discussion with Anoop Mahajan and Gyanam Dave was of great help in
putting this paper together. So was some significant work by Paul Postal on
antipassives; although my thinking has not yet reached a stage where I can
tackle his facts, I should make my personal debt to him – for sending me his
work and for discussing many issues with me – clear. My debt to Richie Kayne is
clear from the text, surely.
Labels: arkiva dokumento / archival document, sintakso / syntax
0 Comments:
Post a Comment
Subscribe to Post Comments [Atom]
<< Home