Compositionality, the Prose Default and Poetry: A Cognitive Approach
Published in International Journal of Mind, Brain and Cognition 1:2.55-76. 2010.
Abstract
Generative
linguistics has been operating with an unexamined default: generically
unspecified prose is taken to constitute the unmarked mode of linguistic composition
from which marked, literary genres depart. This contrasts with what Jakobson’s
structuralist account took to be the conceptual default. His account argued for
poetic patterns (some of them salient, some attenuated) pervading all discourses;
it needs to be superseded by an explicit generative anchoring of
compositionality in fundamental properties of language. To make formalistic
assumptions – a lexico-grammatically driven sound-meaning pairing plus pragmatic
and stylistic supplements – misses the point that every spoken or written
passage is minimally a composition under specifiable generic conventions. This
paper, extending the substantivist conceptual framework in generative grammar,
proposes a ‘Juxtapose Alpha’ operation with consequences for how the
syntagmatic and paradigmatic axes align as sequences of strings are woven into
texts differently for different genres. Certain testable consequences follow
and are of cognitive interest.
1. Introduction
The contextualization of language within human cognition
calls for clarification of the interfaces where language meets other cognitive
systems. Mukherji (2000) sheds some light on the linguistics-musicology
interface. Dasgupta (2003b) notes one crucial conceptual difficulty with his enterprise
in its present form. Music is an art; language is taken to be an ordinary human
phenomenon that happens to provide the material basis for literature. Linguists
base their formalizations on this received wisdom.
One way to take Mukherji’s project further might be to
sharpen our formal understanding of literature, which then feeds a research
agenda at the literature-music interface. A second approach is to inquire if we
are working with the right idealization in our linguistics. Such inquiry
involves rethinking our coordinates and rigorously deepening the basis of
linguistics to the point where formal predictions about literature follow from that
deeper characterization of language. In this article I take the second approach.
Specifically, I make some moves towards a reconsideration of compositionality.
The paper is organized as follows. Section 2 suggests
that the existing take on compositionality, based on a lexico-grammatically
driven sound-meaning pairing with a pragmatics that cleans up afterwards, is excessively
preliminary; that it misses the point that every spoken or written passage is,
as a composition, subject to generic conventions whose formal properties must
be part of the characterization of that passage. Section 3 revisits Jakobson’s
classic work on these issues and inquires how best to update it in a generative
context. Section 4 proposes one way to perform some of this updating. Section 5
returns to the discussion of compositionality and looks at some consequences
for cognitive inquiry.
2. Compositionality
Cutting across major disagreements over every domain
of linguistic analysis, certain default assumptions regarding compositionality
underpin current descriptions of sentences and their phrasal constituents. The
summary of these assumptions provided at (1) below may serve as a point of
departure. These views represent the received wisdom underlying most linguistic,
psychological and philosophical work on language now current.
(1) STC, for Standard Theses on
Compositionality
A sentence is a body of sound and meaning whose
pairing is mediated by grammar plus lexicon. The structure and interpretation
of each sentence are built stepwise; multi-word constructions merge with each other
until the sentence is ready. The interpretation of idiomatic constructions like
kick the bucket ‘die’ takes a special route and requires lexical
registration. Every non-idiomatic construction is a free expression. Its
meaning is jointly determined by the individual senses of its constituents filtered
through the function associated with the construction assembling the parts into
this particular whole. This joint determination principle is termed
compositionality. Such determination of composite meanings exhausts the
lexico-grammatical contribution to the interpretation of sentences and their
constituents. Other aspects of their interpretation reflect such extra-grammatical
factors as pragmatics. The lexico-grammatical account of constructions extends
only up to the sentence level. Levels of organization involving more than one
sentence must invoke additional principles.
To be sure, no author has ever claimed a
perfect fit between STC and primary data; on the contrary, mismatches between
(1) and real life are well known. Instances of false starts, anacoluthon and
other consequences of the imperfect implementation of plans, or of multiple
planning wires getting crossed, are thick on the ground. These everyday traffic
jams motivated the distinction between performance and competence (Chomsky
1965).
From Chomsky 1965 onwards, certain authors drawing on
the resources of generative grammar have sometimes also touched upon the use of
language in creative writing and have suggested that such use exemplifies
various types of deviation from lexico-grammatical norms. They assume that there
is nothing systematic for general linguistics to say about those genres of
language use. Deviations in the service of art are to be understood
aesthetically, at some distance from a formal account of the ordinary,
non-artistic structure of language (for one articulation of how such an
aesthetic account may selectively draw upon a formal characterization of
ordinary linguistic structure, see Fabb 2009). In other words, core linguistics
studies ordinary language as observed in its moderately careful uses. A hasty
person’s careless speech or writing and a literary artist’s deviously careful
writing are both to be set aside in core linguistics. The sloppily careless and
the craftily careful depart from the ordinary in opposite ways; they both count
as inappropriate input for the systematic study of normal knowledge of
language.
This received view, though coherent, misses
a fundamental point about the characterization it implies of the moderately
careful production and comprehension that this approach accepts as the
appropriate object of linguistic study. A person whose language use is neither sloppy
(notably artless) nor creative (notably artful) needs to be viewed as a
moderately successful pedestrian practitioner of the art of verbal
composition. Thus, the lexico-grammatical approach to language left to its own
devices is inadequate, if the task is indeed to characterize language at the
level at which compositionality operates. Contrary to what (1) suggests, the
lexico-grammatical apparatus alone, even with some help from pragmatics, cannot
adequately characterize verbal composition, for such composition is minimally
artistic and this fact affects the construction of meaning.
When one produces a (spoken or written) sentence, one is
doing more; one is composing a minimal but genre-specified passage of prose or
poetry. A description of verbal composition that confines itself to a
naturalistic prose default and to this end elides generic conventions or leaves
them implicit is non-explanatory. By implying such a default, it begs major questions.
To require some supplementary account to bear the burden would be disingenuous,
as no known characterization of performance or pragmatics can reinvent the
literary wheel. The fact that language is an art in some pretheoretical sense awaiting
rigorous elaboration needs to be faced. Thus, we need an account of verbal
composition that does not disengage the lexico-grammatical apparatus from the
rest of the architecture. STC as formulated at (1) cannot underwrite such an
account.
If linguistic theory has to expand to meet this
challenge, just where is the ‘literary element’ of ‘ordinary’ verbal
composition to be niched? To rock the boat too violently would mean losing decades’
worth of work. But we also cannot afford to house new proposals in an optional
‘literary genres’ module of human knowledge of language, thus formalizing the
naive belief that certain ‘non-literary’ verbal compositions are not generically
specified at all. The strategy I follow in this paper involves introducing a
core device into the lexico-grammar in a way that enables our new moves to preserve
continuity with earlier work.
In particular, I propose – generalizing from the Look
Across operation of Dasgupta (2003a) – that the lexico-grammar employs a
juxtaposition operation. The basic functions of this formal operation Juxtapose
Alpha, which works at the same level of generality as Affect Alpha, are
described briefly in section 2 and at greater length in the Appendix. Juxtapose
Alpha has the effect of highlighting a linguistic item and inviting
comparison with similar items in the passage. The linguistic formulation we
provide allows for some latitude of interpretation in terms of pragmatics and other
theories that contextualize language in cognition or action; I return to
broader cognitive science issues in section 5. The Juxtapose operation is
designed to address the issue of ‘parallel constructions’ in the sense of
Chomsky’s (1972) remarks, to which I return in section 2.
The relevance to poetry is obvious. But how can such a
move serve to bring out the latent minimal artistry in all language use? My
answer is to have Juxtapose apply at the moment of enunciation to the
(prototypically sentential) product of grammar that a speaker or writer
enounces; ‘utterance’ is the term for enunciation preferred in a speech-focused
mode of description; in poetry, the descriptive problem one will have to solve as
one elaborates such a framework is that of aligning acts of enouncing with
verse structure.
The decision to apply Juxtapose at this interface follows
the tenets of substantivism (Dasgupta, Ford & Singh 2000; Dasgupta 2010) as
distinct from formalism. But, given the existence of focal stress, and
syntactic effects as in John dóes love Mary, formalists too must use
Juxtapose or some equivalent. For instance, derivationalists committed to sideward
movement (to which I return in section 5) may consider making Juxtapose an
add-on to Spellout or to specified applications of Merge, guided by principles
of economy. This point does not concern formalists alone; substantivist work
also recognizes applications of the routine that target units smaller than the
entire enunciation (Dasgupta 2003c).
Going beyond generalities, Juxtapose serves both to
anchor certain pattern properties of language use in fundamental features of
language design (see section 4 for discussion) and to articulate generic
distinctions. The observations that guide us in this domain begin at versified
poetry: verses are known to depend for their effects on a meshing of salient
patterns that co-deploys recurrence with other properties. Equally crucially, different
genres of prose configure salient patterns differently to produce convention-governed
logical contours in the service of generic effectiveness. This subdomain is
less clearly understood; Ducrot (1984) locates the fundamental problem at
embedding itself; his suggestive descriptions at the pragmatics-grammar
interface flesh out the idea that even embedded finite clauses count as
enunciations. Following his lead, I propose that every finite clause is an
enunciation and triggers a distinct application of Juxtapose.
Assuming that this PF/LF articulation of the task expresses
the natural cuts, I propose module-anchored applications of Juxtapose.
Versification involves prosodically intermeshed applications anchored in the PF
(Phonetic Form) module, while LF (Logical Form) anchored applications address the
dynamics of prose. The point that rhyme is not just a matter of phonology – but
of phonological framing that highlights also the lexical semantics of rhyming
words – does not make it inappropriate to postulate PF anchoring for
applications of Juxtapose responsible for the specificity of verse. PF representations
do not draw on phonetics alone, but access other grammatical features as well.
How does all this bear on showing (1) to be inadequate,
though? Whenever one composes a sentence or a longer passage, it is generically
specified. Such specifications have to do with the pattern of applications of
the Juxtaposition operation available for a particular genre. Thus, a given
sentence (which STC would have us construe only in terms of a sound-meaning
pairing mediated by the lexico-grammar) must in fact also be seen as
constituting, or as being part of, a generically specified passage that deploys
juxtapositions and thus situates several overt subpassages relative to other overt
or covert subpassages on the paradigmatic axis, thereby pointing the meanings
in certain directions and not others relative to the body of presuppositions
that a passage – or even a minimal passage, called a sentence – negotiates with.
This is the level at which (1) fails as a characterization of the factors
determining interpretation and at which Juxtapose helps us to do better.
The idea that semantic interpretation in generative
grammar must incorporate machinery oriented to parallelism is quite old. A
first draft of this approach to linguistic structure in the context of
generative grammar is implicit in Chomsky’s (1972: 90ff) account of focus and
presupposition, read in the light of his observation about “parallel
constructions” (1972: 99) and his comment that a linguistics of competence that
moves away from its Saussurean roots must “drop the loose and metaphoric use of
such notions as ‘choice’” (1972: 116) and must therefore abandon the naively
successivist image of the spoken chain. As we turn those remarks of Chomsky’s
into a serious modification of the generative research programme, it pays to
actually go back to the structuralist image of language, take stock of what was
then understood about “parallel constructions” and the paradigmatic axis, and
do our updating with some clarity about just what is being replaced and why.
This is the agenda of section 3.
3. Revisiting
Jakobson
The importance of the artistic dimension of
language was pointed up quite early by Edward Sapir; he described language
(1921: 231) as “the collective art of expression”; in his framework this was neither
a mere figure of speech nor a statement about a dispensable aspect of some uses
of language. But the most influential formulations by structural linguists in
this domain come from the Prague School. We can usefully focus on an often
cited one-line summary of these formulations – Jakobson’s proposal (1960/1972:
95) that “The poetic function projects the principle of equivalence from the
axis of selection into the axis of combination. [Italicized by Jakobson.]
Equivalence is promoted to the constitutive device of the sequence.”
Jakobson explicates this ‘equivalence’ in terms of
phonetic-semantic similarity and dissimilarity: “Briefly, equivalence in sound,
projected into the sequence as its constitutive principle, inevitably involves
semantic equivalence, and on any linguistic level any constituent of such a
sequence prompts one of the two correlative experiences which Hopkins neatly
defines as ‘comparison for likeness’ sake’ and ‘comparison for unlikeness’
sake’” (1960/1972: 109). The import of these ideas becomes obvious in studies
implementing his model, which need not detain us here; for one iconic
implementation that examines a poem by Baudelaire, see Jakobson and Lévi-Strauss
(1962/1972).
What is more pertinent to projects we can
meaningfully take up in a cognitive science context today is Jakobson’s claim
that the ‘poetic’ function of language in his sense of the term is not confined
to poetry, but bears on all uses of language. He claims that there is no
style-free referential use of language, just as there can be no reference-free
purely poetic use. Even in banal prose passages, where the role of paradigmatic
equivalences projected onto the syntagmatic axis is hardly obvious, Jakobson detects
minimal devices. Their very minimalness makes them less amenable to parallelism-focused
description. But Jakobson’s take is that nonetheless it is precisely devices of
this general sort, however subtle or attenuated, that count as the stylistically
relevant properties of every stretch of speaking or writing.
Thus, Jakobson speaks of “literary forms [in which] verbal
devices are unostentatious and language seems a nearly transparent garment. But
one must say with Charles Sanders Peirce: ‘This clothing never can be
completely stripped off, it is only changed for something more diaphanous’ ([Peirce
1931/1974:] p. 171). ‘Verseless composition’, as Hopkins calls the prosaic
variety of verbal art – where parallelisms are not so strictly marked and
strictly regular as ‘continuous parallelism’ and where there is no dominant
figure of sound – present more entangled problems for poetics” (1960/1972: 116).
Jakobson sees his account of parallelism as offering a valid structural
analysis of the pervasive presence of stylistic devices – of which hard-core poetic
devices are the clearest embodiments and are thus easiest to detect – throughout
all uses of language.
At first blush, it might look puzzling that his
analysis sees poetic devices as the prototypical mode of stylization, most
obviously present in poetry but pervasive throughout all speech and writing. If
one is to postulate any default mode of language use at all, naturalistic prose
is surely the candidate that linguists have always agreed upon. Even Jakobson
never made the perverse claim that versified poetry was the default mode of
language use. Why then did his intuitions as a grammarian lead him to view the
use of poetic devices as prototypical at the level of the structure of language?
When we look at the question more carefully, this
apparent contradiction leads us to question our initial belief that the
observational default status of naturalistic prose somehow revealed the nature
of language – as if language were somehow coextensive with daily communication,
as if it wore its nature on its sleeve. The following facts lead us to
conjecture that poetry is central to language, not an optional ornament. First
of all, poetry is a universal found in all speech communities. Secondly, child
rearing practices everywhere include the use of nursery rhymes, lullabies and
other versified material; the fact that children take to them naturally suggests
that poetry feeds language acquisition. Thirdly, had humans not been specially
designed to find it easy to perceive and digest verses, we should find them as
difficult as jumping through arbitrary hoops, but we find them easy, which is
explained if poetry is built into the language faculty. Fourthly, the earliest
major authors in most literatures composed in verse; prose writing developed
only afterwards and on the formal basis of that poetic corpus.
For these reasons, we need to retain Jakobson’s sense
of the key role that poetry plays in language somewhere in our account even as
we update our perspective. At the same time, surely naturalistic prose is
indeed the default genre if there is one, and surely Chomsky is right to
recommend dropping “the loose and metaphoric use of such notions as ‘choice’”
(1972: 116) that underlies Jakobson’s entire architecture, and therefore to
update our conceptualization of the syntagmatic and paradigmatic axes. How do
we go about balancing these considerations as we reexamine his work?
Jakobson’s point about the irreducibility of stylized
generic conventions stands; a genre-free composition would be a contradiction
in terms. Linguists working with an idealization that claims to set generic
conventions aside tacitly restrict themselves to default genre data; and ‘verseless
composition’ is indeed the default genre. But Jakobson’s portrayal of this
default overplays the poetry card by implying that surface features of
versification are detectable all over language at various degrees of
attenuation; this claim holds only because he underspecifies those features.
The crucial difficulty with his work becomes apparent
in his remarks about “intentional discrepancy between the metrical and
syntactic division” (1960/1972: 107) in the case of “a heavy enjambment which
puts a verse boundary before the concluding monosyllable of a phrase, of a
sentence, of an utterance” (1960/1972: 106). His remarks focus on sophisticated
deviations from the norm of canonical versification; but he leaves it up to the
intelligent reader to supply an account of the norm itself – a job that the
structuralist apparatus even at its best was never suitable for, because it was
excessively wedded to the metaphor of ‘choice’.
Jakobson’s poetics worked around such key words as “from
the axis of selection into the axis of combination” – referring to
Saussurean choice. This confirms Chomsky’s (1972: 115) diagnosis of
structuralism as a paradigm committed to the model of successive linear choices
from finite sets. This fundamental commitment lets Jakobson down even when he works
hard to attain descriptive adequacy. He writes, for example: “The superinducing
of an equivalence principle upon the word sequence or, in other terms, the mounting
[italicization Jakobson’s] of the metrical form upon the usual speech form,
necessarily gives the experience of a double, ambiguous shape to anyone who is
familiar with the given language and with verse. Both the convergences and the
divergences between the two forms, both the warranted and the frustrated
expectations, supply this experience” (1960/1972: 106). Here Jakobson is trying
to portray accurately such effects as ‘warranted and frustrated expectations’
in the reader’s ‘experience’. But a linguistics of effects obstructs the
formulation of principles that would distinguish observed effects from possible
but non-occurring effects. His tools can only describe what it sounds like to
his (superbly perceptive) ear, not what is going on.
Let us then move the problem from his period to ours.
4. Updating
Jakobson: A Generative Approach
Earlier, when I proposed Juxtapose, I was
commenting on conditions that a generative analysis of the genre-specified
nature of verbal composition must meet. At that point I made no attempt to
engage with empirical material, or even to indicate what types of description
and explanation are at stake. To seriously update Jakobson means moving his
perceptive engagement with the data into methods of analysis consistent with generative
grammar in particular and cognitive inquiry in general. The point is to attain
higher degrees of descriptive and explanatory adequacy rather than just old
wine in new bottles. To this end, we must engage with certain fundamental
properties of language, showing how they underpin verbal compositions in
specific genres.
The novelty of free expressions is a
property of direct relevance. It is a fact about the creative aspect of
language use that speaker S uttering free expression FE in context C is
offering FE as an appropriate and novel contribution to what there is to say
given C. It is possible for FE to be novel even if the set to which it belongs,
S(FE), is finite but large: a particular FE may happen to fall outside the
range of what the hearer has heard before, or of what has been said with
respect to C. If FE is drawn from an infinite S(FE), the probability of any
particular FE having been used before drops to zero, giving us a formal basis
for regarding any arbitrary FE as a novel contribution. This is why, in our
thinking about the novelty property, we often associate it with the infinity of
sentences – the flip side of the fact that a sentence can be as long as one
pleases, with no upper bound. But this association, as we normally state it,
takes only the syntagmatic axis on board and considers only sentence-length
Free Expressions.
If we consider an FE smaller than a sentence but
participating in a rhyming relation, we can associate its novelty with infinity
along paradigmatic lines, thus beginning to use the space that Juxtapose
creates for us. Hence my decision to concentrate on poetry at this stage of the
discussion. Assume conservatively, for argument’s sake, that the set of
subsentential FEs in English (or some otherwise characterized set to which an
FE we are considering belongs) is large but finite. In other words, suppose
that our intuitions about possible poems, reader responses etc. make it
reasonable to claim that no line of verse can be longer than, say, sixty
syllables. Even so, the FE their green felicity in the Keats poem
fragment (2) below – evidently a finite-sized object – counts as a member of a
rhyme-set S(FE) whose initial members are too happy, happy tree and
their green felicity. This two-member rhyme-set is indefinitely extendable,
by adding an FE′, an FE′′, etc.; overt addition, part of the labour of writing
a long poem, may have some psychologically determinate upper limit if it turns
out that humans cannot respond to any epic that trumps the Mahabharata’s 200000
verses; but intertextuality invokes covert members of S(FE). Thus even on
conservative assumptions a subsentential FE, considered as a member of a
rhyme-set S(FE), is formally associable with infinity along the same lines as a
sentence is. As all producers and consumers of poetry know, a line in a poem
does not carry its meaning alone, but in the context of one poem in particular
and poetry in general, a property only crudely quasi-formalized by placing it
in an S(FE):
(2) In a drear-nighted December,
Too happy, happy Tree,
Thy branches ne’er remember
Their green felicity:
The north cannot undo them
With a sleety whistle through them,
Nor frozen thawing glue them
From budding at the prime. (Keats
1971: 195)
Summarizing, I am saying of an as yet unspecified
unit, provisionally labelled as ‘a line of a poem’, that it is part of a potentially
infinite paradigmatic set, and that this property helps make sense of the fact
that uttering the line is a novel contribution to some context C in relation to
which one utters the line. I am proposing that this novelty parallels the
novelty of a sentence as understood in terms of the infinity of the set of
sentences.
It becomes easier to discuss this parallelism if I
redescribe a ‘line of a poem’ as an RC-String, a minimal bearer of an RC
(a rhythm contour). RC-Strings and Sentences are two types of vehicle
that share certain fundamental properties across the prose-poetry boundary. But
my account leaves the boundary intact. What has been said already differentiates
poetry from prose, but gives us a new basis for exploring shared properties.
Rhythm is constitutive of each line of poetry, of each RC-String, which
formally counts as novel to the extent that rhyme (or some other factor
responsible for rhyme-set analogues) places it in a potentially infinite set.
Now suppose that every vehicle, in order to carry
novelty, must be anchored in the familiar and must fly a novel kite. Call the
pertinent segments its Anchor and its Kite – assuming, for
concreteness, that the anchoring and kiting functions are always best served by
postulating bounded segments rather than non-localized relations between the
vehicle and its context. In the case of the Sentence, the Topic/Comment divide
is familiar; we hereby identify it as instantiating anchor/kite in prose. For the
RC-String, we shall not multiply terms beyond necessity, but stick to Anchor
and Kite. Crucially, in both vehicle types, the anchor comes first and the kite
follows.
Given these decisions, it now becomes possible to take
up an empirical issue. The familiar poetic device exemplified in text (2)
above, rhyme, involves a couple of sounds at the end of one line of verse
echoing those at the end of an earlier line. Now consider (3) and (4), written flippantly
to make the formal point that such passages, where the mirror image of the
rhyme constraint holds, do not instantiate a possible natural language
versification system –
(3) Sliding downhill is a choice, but
Sly apostles terrify us;
Forty winters hit your brow when
Forsythe goons hold these kids hostage.
Age-old perils circumscribe us:
Aimless jaunts deplete our assets.
Why try serious moves? We always
Whine our way past danger, don’t we?
(4) For all the fake tears that you shed now
Will not revive a single victim.
Forget it: you are always lethal.
We have no choice – we hate and fear
you.
Sweet talk brought us under your
shadow;
Yet our sangfroid will pull us
through.
Swedes tricked us into losing hope:
Yemenis will restore our glory.
These texts have
been written to illustrate Mirror Image Rhyme, MIR. This device involves a
couple of initial sounds of one line of verse echoing the initial sounds of either
the immediately preceding line, as in (3), or the relevant preceding line in such
a rhyme pattern as the ABAB scheme in (4). By MIR I mean a system distinct from
the empirically attested device of Initial Alliteration, whose relatively
common word-initial variant is exemplified in Four faithful friends
fought for the fairest flame. As a formal exercise, MIR falls within the
range of the learning capacity of poets and readers. People play acrostics and
other verse games; to find a niche for MIR in a baroque system is not a
cognitive or cultural impossibility. But apparently no culture, in fact, uses
MIR as the default on which its poetic device architecture rests. This
phenomenon calls for an explanation. The outline account I am offering in this
paper begins to provide one. Prima facie the No MIR Default Hypothesis, NMDH,
is empirically confirmed across the board. Why does NMDH hold?
The account rudimentarily developed here
suggests the answer that rhyme, which ties one RC-String to other RC-Strings, is
a focalizing device and needs to appear in the Kite part of the RC-String; for
that is where a recurring salient sound sequence can be noticed as part of the vehicle’s
novel contribution. If we were to tuck a focalizing device away in the Anchor segment,
as required under MIR, it would become unnoticeable and impossible to use as
the structural basis for the paradigmatic sets organizing the poem. This
explanation holds fundamental principles of language design responsible for the
typological unavailability of MIR as a default principle in a poetic system.
MIR is available for games, but cannot serve as the default device making poetry
tick throughout a language the way rhyme can. On these assumptions, Initial
Alliteration is available as a poetic organizing device because it autosegmentally
‘spreads’ all over the RC-String, subsuming the Kite as well.
I offer this tentative explanation
(elaborated below) as an indication that the programme can be made to work. But
I am doing this at the level of quickly sketching a pursuable path through a
relatively uncharted terrain. As we take real possession of the terrain, we
will have to provide an account of the point Jakobson missed, an account of the
normal convergence, in poetry, of syntactic constituents with RC-Strings, from
which enjambement is a marked departure. Making Juxtapose target constituents
will not suffice. When Juxtapose targets a sentence P with complex internal
structure, we get P associating with {P′, P′′…}, but supplementary principles
will have to say if P-internal constituents invite distinct applications of
Juxtapose. Economy or optimality principles will need to manage that traffic,
which is where enjambement gets characterized as a departure from some statable
default.
To call the terrain even relatively
uncharted is somewhat inaccurate and may offend. I hasten to add that I mean
the terrain of deriving descriptively significant properties of generic
conventions from fundamental principles; it would be absurd to deny the
abundance of observations, of intriguing generalizations, of methodological
suggestions. In that literature, there is a pertinent point that I must address
to complete my remarks on MIR. Fabb (2010), citing an earlier paper of his,
reports that “Fabb (1999) argues for a distinction between alliteration and
rhyme: alliteration holds between adjacent sections of text, but rhyme need not
(and so can form ABAB patterns, unlike alliteration). On this basis, we would
classify the Finnish and Mongolian onset+nucleus repetitions as alliteration
because they are strictly local (within the line, or between adjacent lines),
and not classified as (reverse) rhyme.”
The desire to accommodate the data Fabb provides –
under his illuminating description – within my account is what makes me
speculate that alliteration may require treatment in autosegmental terms. But
obviously what I have said so far leaves the pertinent difference between verse-initial
alliteration and rhyme – that rhyme can have an ABAB variant while line-initial
alliteration cannot – underived from fundamental properties of language. What
would a serious derivation look like?
Recall that Anchor/Kite in verse is an
analogue of Topic/Comment in prose. Suppose we pursue this analogy and make the
working assumption that, wherever a Focus occurs, it is part of the Comment.
Examples of Topic/Comment structure in the syntax include (5) To forgive/ is
divíne and (6) That John will stop smoking/ seems óbvious; at a
pinch, we can embed (6) within format (5) and say (7) [[That to forgive/ is divine]/
seems obvious] – marked, but possible. Note that the structure of
(7) displays a little topic/ little comment structure within the big topic. The
RC String analogue of (7), with anchors and kites, doubles (7) to yield ABAB
rhyme.
Now suppose that line-initial alliteration in
Mongolian is an RC String analogue to (8) It is Jóhn who will stop smoking,
where the Anchor shrinks to near zero (to it is) and the Kite begins
extremely early – at the focal John. Reasoning analogically, we note
that (8) does not give rise to a (7)-like double topic-comment structure, and
we then infer that line-initial alliteration will not support an ABAB pattern.
A serious derivation of the incompatibility of MIR
with ABAB would look like a translation of this bit of analogical reasoning
into the mode of a formal deduction from conceptually explicit premises. In
order to get there, one needs to first create abstract anchor-kite templates
that generalize over topic-comment syntax and anchor-kite poetic structure;
such abstractions will remain unmotivated until the project is demonstrated to
be worthwhile. The point of the present study is to do the demonstrating.
What has been said so far shows that the Juxtapose
Alpha operation and RC Strings endowed with Anchor-Kite structure associate certain
phenomena with fundamental properties of language. Notice too that these devices
implement Chomsky’s suggestion that we avoid the choice metaphor. Juxtapose
places its targets in a paradigmatic space that no longer works in terms of an
item being chosen from a finite set.
But how do such devices, which link vehicles to
infinity so clearly in the case of poetry, help install naturalistic prose as a
generic default? At a first approximation, forcing a Juxtapose whenever a
topic-comment-endowed sentence is enounced means each such sentence stands up
and is counted with all sentences that possibly can or actually do precede or
follow it in the passage. Now that every constituent clause with a
topic-comment structure is associated with an obligatory application of
Juxtapose, note that certain but not all embeddings contribute enunciative
complexity – recall my invocation of Ducrot (1984) in section 2 – and that both
complex sentences and appropriate simple sentence sequences in a coherent prose
passage correspond to strophe structure in verse. These count as prosaic and
poetic instantations of the fundamental recursive property of language.
On the ground, the austerity of applying only
obligatory Juxtapositions also provides the space for questions and answers etc.
to match up and find each other, establishing freely interpreted (rather than
conventionally stylized) isomorphisms and complementarities, thus weaving together
bits of a conversation, or of a conversational turn, or of a prose passage.
With some imagination, readers can relate these remarks to issues concerning
coherence and cohesion. Thus the result of performing just the obligatory
applications of Juxtapose is naturalistic prose, which thus counts as a generic
default.
Where does such an account house the idea that poetry,
though not the default genre, is central to language? At the point that RC
Strings are what happens when PF-anchored applications of Juxtapose settle for
‘optimal’, Goldilocks-sized targets, just big enough to hold a Rhythm Contour and
support Anchor-Kite structure (thus manifesting the fundamental properties of a
vehicle), but just small enough to sponsor a proliferation of juxtaposition
relations in a text.
Why, given this account, should verse loom so large on
a child’s screen? Because the acquisition trajectory puts PF first and LF
second, and at the same time the child needs to acquire the Anchor-Kite
structure and recursion by using the earliest resources available. This
acquisition prepares the child for more intricate Topic-Comment and
Subject-Predicate realizations of Anchor-Kite structure and syntactic
realizations of recursion when it is time to sharpen the tools that nursery
rhymes provide baby versions of.
5. Some Consequences
This section outlines some consequences of
Juxtapose for theories that embed language in cognition and for our understanding
of compositionality.
The minimal artistry of verbal composition,
on the Juxtapose account, lies in so structuring what you say that it is
designed to fit into some context or other. Considering verbal structures purely
syntagmatically and in isolation from context has struck formal linguists as a
rewarding exercise, justified by its spectacular successes. However, every
verbal structure is in fact composed, and every composition wears its
participation in infinity on its sleeve. This participation is partly
syntagmatic – which has been the generative revolution’s primary concern – and
partly paradigmatic, a matter that places language in the realm of the arts.
Generative work, if it is to provide a serious account of the infinity of
language, needs to take the paradigmatic axis of language on board, after
decades of syntagmatically focused work.
The Juxtapose account of these matters is
at one level an amplification of the substantivist alternative to the standard
formalist approach in generative linguistics. In a book-length articulation of substantivism,
Dasgupta, Ford & Singh (2000) argue for the impossibility of any ‘compound
word language’ that consists only of compound word box within compound word
box, forever, and that never builds any true sentences; once that argument is
appropriately extended, it forces us to revise our understanding of compositionality.
Dasgupta, Ford & Singh (2000) focus on the
constitutive importance of the fact that building a sentence calls for morphological
inflection in many languages and abstract syntactic inflection in all languages.
Inflection has been under syntactic investigation for several decades as an
exponent of specifier-head relations. It can be reinterpreted along the lines suggested
in section 4 because specifiers are anchors writ small. The present paper is to
be read as elaborating the core substantivist argument, moving the discussion
from inflection alone to anchor/kite relations in general.
How does the argument, so elaborated, help us to
arrive at a picture of compositionality that does better than the standard
approach given at (1)?
The substantivist argument, even in its
preliminary form, implied (though Dasgupta, Ford & Singh (2000) did not
explicitly state) that the standard take on compositionality made the mistake
of using an abstract sense of ‘part’ and ‘whole’ in the formulation that the
meaning of the whole was a function of the meanings of the parts. As Dasgupta,
Ford & Singh (2000) note, a serious theory of language must predict the
unavailability of compound word languages. But even a counterfactual compound
word language would have parts and wholes. Formulation (1) of compositionality
is compatible even with a counterfactual world that forces language to choose from
finite sets and imposes boundary parameters making the set of all strings
finite. No serious theory can afford to gloss over the point that compositions
are crucially free; and formulation (1) does miss that point.
The elaborated form of the substantivist
argument prompts us to suggest one way of improving on (1). What launches the
linguistic vehicle (as a proseworthy sentence or as a poetryworthy RC-string)
into orbit is its internal Anchor-Kite factorization that dovetails the need to
place the vehicle on the paradigmatic axis with the requirement that the
‘given’ anchor should be responsible for contextualization while the ‘new’
kite, especially its ‘saliently new’ focus, should manage the relation between
the vehicle and its infinitely many paradigmatic companions. The fundamental
language design feature of recursion is the point at which these two needs
meet. The Juxtapose operation, which is what induces Anchor-Kite factorization,
fans out into PF-anchored and LF-anchored applications, which yield the generic
differentiation into prose and poetry with correspondingly distinct types of
factorization – Anchor/Kite proper in poetry and Topic/Comment (projected as
Specifier/Head all the way down the syntactic tree) in prose – and of
instantiations of recursion.
Given such an account, we can replace (1)
with the following formulation of compositionality, or some reformulation that
incorporates a more intricate approach to generic differentiation than we have
the resources to develop here:
(9) A
text is a body of sound and meaning whose pairing is mediated by general grammar,
specific lexicon and conventional combinatorics. The structure and
interpretation of grammatical constructions are assembled stepwise. Such
assembly is guided by integrative processes that simultaneously endow vehicles
of appropriate shape and size with anchor/ kite articulation, aggregate these
vehicles syntagmatically, and project their articulation on to the paradigmatic
axis. This process of aggregation and projection stops at a finite outcome on
the ground but invokes infinity. Every step in the assembly process involves a
joint determination of the meaning of the product by lexical, grammatical and combinatorial
factors. This joint determination principle is termed compositionality. The
integrative processes lean towards phonetic form to yield poetry or lean
towards logical form to yield prose, implementing recursion differently, and
interweaving with such extra-grammatical factors as pragmatics differently.
How do these formal matters bear on other
branches of cognitive inquiry? One obvious type of relevance arises from the
fact that humans grasp a series of actions in terms of its articulations in prose
that verbalizes plans for a future sequence of activities or reports a past
sequence. Philosophy, psychology, artificial intelligence may therefore find it
heuristically useful to relate the conceptualization of action sequences to that
of prose descriptions. If our understanding of the compositional structure of a
prose passage highlights the role of the Topic-Comment organization of each
enunciation, it is natural to ask how this patterning relates to conceptually pertinent
correlates. One such correlate is the figure-ground organization of the
corresponding actions as perceived by the actor or by salient bystanders. Does the
organization of an action sequence – as perceived by some actor or observer –
bring the figure-ground structures of the constituent actions into some form of
interplay that needs to be made explicit? This is one research question for cognitive
science that emerges from the present study.
There are also far more concrete piecemeal
studies that are worth undertaking at the sequel level. In the empirical study
of the psychological properties of poetry and prose, we need to: (a) design
experiments that test the relative learnability of MIR and other crazy rhyme
schemes, as we go about characterizing what is natural and what is crazy in
these and related domains; (b) study the perceptual similarities and
differences between prototypical prose, prototypical poetry, and mixed texts;
(c) examine the age profile at which the crazier patterns and enjambement come
within the growing child’s cognitive reach; (d) cross-fertilize such inquiry
with cultural diversity issues. What makes such study theoretically
significant, however, is the relevance of these matters to recursion.
Our understanding of recursion so far has focused
on sentence embedding. But this is a special case of projecting paradigmatic
facts on to the syntagmatic axis. The present study proposes that the specific
human surplus relative to other primates is such biaxial projection itself,
with sentence embedding and infinite sets of paradigmatically juxtaposed Rhythm
Contour Strings counting as special cases.
Recall the following classic passage about the human
surplus: “Even the best tool for a given problem is lost on the chimpanzee if
it cannot see it simultaneously or quasi-simultaneously with the goal. By
‘quasi-simultaneous perception’ Koehler means instances when tool and goal had been
seen together a moment earlier, or when they had been used together so many
times in an identical situation that they are to all intents and purposes
simultaneously perceived psychologically (Koehler, 1973, pp. 99-100). Thus the
consideration of ‘insight’ does not change our conclusion that the chimpanzee,
even if it possessed the parrot’s gifts, would be exceedingly unlikely to
conquer speech” (Vygotsky 1996: 77-78). We are suggesting, in this paper, that the
paradigmatics of poetry and the syntagmatics of embedded sentences will turn
out to be empirically distinct frontiers that even sign language trained apes
cannot cross, and that theoretical work will show that these two phenomenal
domains reflect the same underlying formal principles.
As such extensions of this research into
cognitive science make some headway, the linguistics of these matters will also
become clearer. For one thing, the ubiquity of EPP (Extended Projection
Principle) phenomena – intriguingly unmotivated by considerations of semantics –
can now be explored on the basis of the factorizations imposed by Juxtapose.
For another, specifying the class of possible syntactic parameters is known to
involve inflection and its concomitants (Borer 1982); we may hope that that
enterprise will flourish again. Besides, syntacticians enamoured of parallel
workspaces, sideward movement and other byproducts of multiple spellout (threads
initiated by Nunes 1999; Uriagereka 1999; Nunes & Uriagereka 2000) may find
syntax-internal uses for Juxtapose proper. Such moves will mean breaching the
frontier between embedding and poetry within formal syntax itself, with
consequences for the way Fabb (2009) configures symmetric and asymmetric
relations in his account of the parasitic relation between poetry and the
generated paraphrase from which it steals an interpretation.
Changing our anchor in linguistics in these ways will
mean flying our cognitive kites differently. We currently lack the resources to
outline with any clarity where these moves will lead; but I hope to have
convinced the reader that we do not have the choice of not exploring them.
Appendix: the
Juxtapose operation
Since Juxtapose
Alpha operates at the same level of generality as Affect Alpha, some readers
may first need to familiarize themselves with how Affect Alpha works in
standard systems of generative grammar.
Most readers are familiar with first generation formal
syntactic devices – with phrase structure rules, such as S à NP VP, and
with syntactic transformations, which either move a constituent (Passivization
moves object to subject, Wh-Movement moves a wh-constituent to the front of the
sentence) or delete a constituent (Imperative Deletion deletes the subject you).
Formally careful second generation syntactic systems
generalize constituent movement rules, arriving at the formulation ‘Move
Alpha’. In those systems, movements in syntax are not stated in the format of
particular rules that encode extraction site and landing site details. Instead,
syntactic principles are invoked, under the guidance of parameters that specify
the way language (sub)types fan out, to explain why the class of extraction
sites and landing sites is what it is in a given language.
Second generation systems similarly subsume all
syntactic deletion and insertion rules under abstract superordinate operations.
‘Affect Alpha’ is the generalization expressing the idea that the syntax can
move/ delete/ insert anything anywhere provided that the fundamental principles
allow those particular applications of the operations. These operations can
apply in the syntax proper, or in the PF (Phonetic Form) module of grammar, or
in its LF (Logical Form) module; the details vary across implementations.
The present study proposes a Juxtapose Alpha operation
at the same level of generality as Affect Alpha. Each time this operation
applies, some item in a passage (a sentence, a line of verse) is given the
supplementary status of a paradigmatic axis neighbour of some corresponding item/s
earlier or later in the passage; this status is supervenient on the structure
that the grammar has already put in place. Every application of Juxtapose
minimally requests the listener/ reader to compare the later and the earlier
items and note in what ways they differ from/ resemble/ complement each other.
Beyond this minimal request, certain applications of Juxtapose, in the PF
module, make the heavier demands involved in versification. Applications of
abstract operations are known to have distinct, module-dependent formal
effects; Affect Alpha in the PF module has linearization properties that its LF
applications lack. One way to implement the anchor-kite idea presented in the
text is to have PF-oriented applications of Juxtapose induce a factorization of
the tree that delineates the kite and highlights its rhyme or other focal
device for managing its paradigmatic neighbourhood. In the case of LF-oriented
applications of Juxtapose, just how this account should deal with Topic-Comment,
Subject-Predicate, and other Specifier-Head dyads that the regular syntax
recognizes is an open question. Different models implementing the programme
proposed here will address the details differently.
Acknowledgements
Support from the
Esperantic Studies Foundation for research on substantivist linguistics and
from the Department of Science and Technology (Government of India) for the
‘Language and Brain Organization in Normative Multilingualism’ project is
gratefully acknowledged. I thank Josef Bayer, Sourin Bhattacharya, Nirmalya
Narayan Chakraborty, Subha Chakraborty Dasgupta, Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak,
Noam Chomsky, Samantak Das, Niladri Sekhar Dash, Sanjukta Dasgupta, Amiya Dev,
Shubhasree Ganguly, Aniket Jaaware, Rajesh Kasturirangan, René Joseph Lavie, Nirmalangshu
Mukherji, Manfred Sailer, Sundar Sarukkai, Gautam Sengupta, Rajendra Singh,
Himanshu Upadhyaya, two anonymous IJMBC reviewers and audiences at the
University of Paris VII (2008) and at the 4th Indo-US Workshop on Science and
Technology (National Institute of Advanced Studies, Bengaluru, 2010) for relevant
responses and comments. I am especially grateful to Narayanan Srinivasan for
serving as ‘acting chief editor’ (to ensure the anonymity of the IJMBC review
process for this submission), to Nigel Fabb for critical input, and to Noam
Chomsky for suggesting I write to Fabb. The usual disclaimers apply.
References
Borer, Hagit. 1982.
Parametric Syntax. Dordrecht: Foris.
Chomsky, Noam.
1965. Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam.
1972. ‘Deep structure, surface structure, and semantic interpretation’. In his Studies
on Semantics in Generative Grammar. The Hague: Mouton. 62-119.
Dasgupta, Probal.
2003a. ‘The sarcastic causative problem and a Look Across solution’. Paper
presented at Conference on Argument Structure, U. of Delhi, 3-5 January.
Dasgupta, Probal.
2003b. Review of Mukherji (2000). Journal of Indian Council for
Philosophical Research 20:2.232-9.
Dasgupta, Probal. 2003c. ‘Antiopacity and Bangla causatives: a
substantivist approach’. In Rajendra Singh, Probal Dasgupta (eds.) The
Yearbook of South Asian Languages and Linguistics 2003. Berlin/ New York:
Mouton de Gruyter. 47-70.
Dasgupta, Probal.
2010. ‘Laaloner jabaan’ [in Bangla; ‘the language of Lalan Fakir’s poetry’]. Manuscript,
forthcoming in Arshinagar.
Dasgupta, Probal;
Ford, Alan; Singh, Rajendra. 2000. After Etymology: Towards a Substantivist
Linguistics. Muenchen: Lincom Europa.
Ducrot, Oswald.
1984. Le dire et le dit. Paris: Minuit.
Fabb, Nigel.
1999. ‘Verse constituency and the locality of alliteration’. Lingua
108:223-245.
Fabb, Nigel. 2009. ‘Symmetric and asymmetric relations, and the
aesthetics of form in poetic language’. European English Messenger 18:1.50-59.
Fabb, Nigel. 2010.
‘Is literary language a development of ordinary language?’ Lingua 120:5.1219-1232.
Jakobson, Roman.
‘Linguistics and poetics’. In Thomas A. Sebeok (ed.) 1960. Style in Language.
Cambridge: MIT Press. Reprinted in Richard DeGeorge, Fernande DeGeorge (eds.) The
Structuralists: From Marx to Lévi-Strauss. Garden City, NY: Anchor Books.
85-122.
Jakobson, Roman;
Lévi-Strauss, Claude. ‘Charles Baudelaire’s “Les Chats”’. In Richard DeGeorge,
Fernande DeGeorge (eds.) The Structuralists: From Marx to Lévi-Strauss.
Garden City, NY: Anchor Books. 124-46. [Tr of ‘“Les Chats” de Charles
Baudelaire’, L’Homme 2:1.5-21, 1962. Tr by Richard and Fernande
DeGeorge, tr rev by Roman Jakobson.]
Keats, John.
‘Happy Insensibility’. 1971. In: Francis Turner Palgrave (ed.) The Golden
Treasury of English Songs and Lyrics. London: Dent. 195.
Koehler, Wolfgang.
1973. The Mentality of Apes. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Mukherji,
Nirmalangshu. 2000. The Cartesian Mind: Reflections on Language and Music.
Shimla: Indian Institute of Advanced Studies.
Nunes, Jairo.
1999. ‘Linearization of chains and phonetic realization of chain links’. In:
Samuel Epstein, Norbert Hornstein (eds.) Working Minimalism. Cambridge:
MIT Press. 217-50.
Nunes, Jairo;
Uriagereka, Juan. 2000. ‘Cyclicity and extraction domains’. Syntax 3:1.20-43.
Peirce, Charles
Sanders. 1931. Collected Papers. Ed. Charles Harteshorne, Paul Weiss.
Vol. 1. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. [Repr 1974.]
Sapir, Edward.
1921. Language: An Introduction to the Study of Speech. New York:
Harcourt, Brace and World.
Uriagereka, Juan.
1999. ‘Multiple spell-out’. In: Samuel Epstein, Norbert Hornstein (eds.) Working
Minimalism. Cambridge: MIT Press. 251-82.
Vygotsky, Lev.
1996. Thought and Language. Tr. Alex Kozulin. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press.